Final Review
Updated 2017-12-17
Chapter 1
Set
- Denoted by \(\{\}\)
- Element in the set: \(1\in \{1, 2\}\)
- Subset: \(\{1\}\subset \{1,2\}\)
Power Set
Suppose \(A=\{1, 2\}\) then its power set is a set of all subsets of \(A\): \(\mathcal P(A)=\{\emptyset, \{1\}, \{2\}, \{1, 2\}\}\)
Set Operations
Suppose sets \(A=\{1,2,3\}, B=\{3, 4, 5\}\)
Union
If \(x\in A\) or \(x\in B\) then \(x\in A \cup B\)
Intersection
If \(x\in A\) and \(x\in B\) then \(x \in A\cap B\)
Difference
If \(x\in A\) and \(x\notin B\) then \(x\in A-B\)
Compliment
If \(x\in A\) then \(x\notin \bar A\)
Direct Product
Direct product of two sets is \(A\times B\) that outputs an ordered set \((a, b)\) such that \(a\in A, b\in B\).
Indexed Sets Operations
Union
\[\bigcup_{i=1}^{n}A_i=A_1\cup A_2\cup A_3\cup \dots\]Intersection
\[\bigcap_{i=1}^{n}A_i=A_1\cap A_2\cap A_3\cap \dots\]Chapter 2
Statement
A statement is a claim. A statement can be true or false.
Logical Operations
Conjunction
Binary operator also known as and. Denoted by \(\wedge\). Suppose \(A\) and \(B\) are statements \(A\wedge B\) is true if and only if \(A\) and \(B\) are both true.
Disjunction
Binary operator also known as or. Denoted by \(\vee\). \(A\vee B\) is true if \(A\) is true, \(B\) is true, or both is true.
Negation
Denoted by \(\neg\). If \(A=\neg B\), then \(A\) is true if and only if \(B\) is false.
Open Sentence
A statement that can’t be determined to be true or false unless a quantifier is given. An example would be:
- \(x\) is an even number.
Logical Equivalences
DeMorgan
\[\neg (A\cap B)=\neg A\cup \neg B\]Distributive
\[A\cap(B\cup C)=(A\cap B)\cup(A\cap C)\]Implications
Implication: \(P\implies Q\)
Converse: \(Q\implies P\)
Contrapositive: \(\neg Q \implies \neg P\)
Negation: \(\neg (P\implies Q)\equiv \neg P \wedge Q\)
Biconditional Implications
Also referred to as “if and only if”
\[P\iff Q\equiv (P\implies Q)\wedge(Q\implies P)\]Quantifier
An example of quantifiers to the open sentence example (above) would be:
- \(\forall x\in \mathbb N\) (this would make the statement false)
- \(\exists x\in \mathbb N\) (this would make the statement true)
Negation
\[\neg \forall \equiv \exists,\quad \neg \exists \equiv \forall\]Chapter 4-10
Direct Proof
To prove \(P\implies Q\), the structure is:
\[\begin{align} &\text{Assume P is true}\\ &\vdots\\ &\text{Therefore Q is true} \end{align}\]Proof By Cases
Usually use when there there is a disjunction in the proof.
Proof By Contrapositive
To prove \(P\implies Q\), the structure is:
\[\begin{align} &\text{Assume Q is false}\\ &\vdots\\ &\text{Therefore P is false} \end{align}\]Proof By Contradiction
To prove \(P\implies Q\), the structure is:
\[\text{Assume the hypothesis is negated}: \neg Q \wedge P,\\ \vdots\\ \text{finds contradiction}\\ \text{Therefore the negated statement is false (original hypothesis is true)}\]Existence Proof
To prove \(\exists x, R(x)\), where \(R(x)\) is the statement. Just provide an example.
Uniqueness Proof
To prove \(\exists x, R(x)\), \(x\) is unique, provide an example \(x=d\) for which \(R(d)\) is true (existence proof) and show that \(d\) is the only unique example.
Constructive Proof
Gives an explicit example that proves and existence proof.
Non-Constructive Proof
Proves an example exists without actually providing it.
Mathematical Induction
Proof By Induction
To prove the statements \(S_1, S_2, S_2\dots\) are all true, the structure is:
\[\begin{align} &\textbf{(basis step)}\text{ Prove }S_1\text{ is true}\\ &\textbf{(induction step)}\text{ Given any integer } k\geq1, \text{Prove } S_k\implies S_{k+1}\\ &\vdots\\ &\text{By induction hypothesis...}\\ &\vdots\\ &\text{Therefore }S_n\text{ is true} \end{align}\]Strong Mathematical Induction
Strong induction works the same as regular induction, except:
- instead of assuming \(S_k\) is true, we assume \(S_1, S_2,\dots, S_k\) all to be true.
Proof By Smallest Counterexample
This is a hybrid of proving by induction and proving by contradiction. To prove \(S_1, S_2, \dots\) are all true, the structure is:
\[\begin{align} \textbf{(basis)}&\text{ Prove } S_1 \text{ is true}\\ \textbf{(contradict)}& \text{ For the sake of contradiction, assume not every }S_n\text{ is true}\\ &\text{Let smallest integer }k>1 \text{ such that } S_k \text{ is false}\\ &\text{Then }S_{k-1} \text{ is true and } S_k \text{ is false; get contradiction} \end{align}\]Chapter 11
Relation
Definition: a relation \(R\), on a set \(A\) is a subset \(R\subset A\times A\).
Relation Properties
- Relation \(R\) is reflexive iff \(\forall x \in A, xRx\)
- Relation \(R\) is symmetric iff \(\forall x, y\in A, xRy\implies yRx\)
- Relation \(R\) is transitive iff \(\forall x, y, z\in A, ((xRy)\wedge(yRz))\implies xRz\)
Equivalence Relation
A relation \(R\) is an equivalence relation iff \(R\) is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive.
Equivalence Class
Equivalence relations on \(A\) divides \(A\) into subsets called equivalence class. The equivalence class containing \(a\) is the subset \(\{x\in A:xRa\}\) of \(A\) consists of all elements of \(A\) that relates to \(a\).
- Denoted as \([a]\)
- Where \([a]=\{x\in A: xRa\}\)
- If there exists \([a]=[b]\), there is still only one equivalence class.
Theorem 11.1: Suppose \(R\) is an equivalence relation on set \(A\) and \(a,b\in A\). Then \([a]=[b]\) iff \(aRb\)
Partition
A partition of set \(A\) is a set of non-empty subsets of \(A\) such that the union of all subsets equals \(A\) and intersection of any two subsets equals \(\emptyset\).
Theorem 11.2: Suppose \(R\) is an equivalence relation on set \(A\). Then the set \(\{[a]:a\in A\}\) forms a partition of \(A\).
Integer Modulo n
The equivalence classes of the equivalence relation \(\equiv (\text{mod } n)\) are \([0], [1], \dots, [n-1]\), for some \(n\in \mathbb N\). Then the integer modulo n is the set \(\mathbb Z_n=\{[0], [1], \dots, [n-1]\}\).
- Property 1: \([a]+[b]=[a+b]\)
- Property 2: \([a]\cdot[b]=[a\cdot b]\)
Chapter 12
Function
- A function is denoted as \(f:A\rightarrow B\), where \(A\) is the domain and \(B\) is the codomain
- The range of function \(f\) is the set \(\{f(a):a\in A\}=b:(a,b)\in f\)
- Two functions \(f\) and \(g\) are the same iff \(\forall x\in A, f(x)=g(x)\)
Injective
A function is injective iff \(\forall x,y\in A, x\neq y\implies f(x)\neq f(y)\).
To prove a function is injective, the proof structure is (contrapositive):
\[\begin{align} &\text{Suppose }x,y\in A \text{ and } f(x)=f(y)\\ &\vdots\\ &\text{Therefore x=y} \end{align}\]Surjective
A function is surjective iff \(\forall b\in B, \exists a\in A\) such that \(f(a)=b\)
To prove a function is surjective, the proof structure is (direct):
\[\begin{align} &\text{Suppose } b\in B\\ &\vdots\\ &\text{*Existential proof for } \exists a\in A \text{ for which } f(a)=b* \end{align}\]Bijective
A function bijective iff the function is both injective and surjective
Pigeonhole Principle
Suppose \(A\) and \(B\) are finite sets and \(f:A\rightarrow B\) is any function, then:
- If \(\lvert A \rvert >\lvert B\rvert\) then \(f\) is not injective
- If \(\lvert A \rvert <\lvert B\rvert\) then \(f\) is not surjective
Suppose \(A\) and \(B\) are finite sets and \(A\neq \emptyset, B\neq \emptyset\), then:
- If \(\lvert A \rvert \geq \lvert B \rvert\) then \(\exists\) a surjective \(f:A\rightarrow B\)
- If \(\lvert A \rvert \leq\lvert B \rvert\) then \(\exists\) an injective \(g:A\rightarrow B\)
- If \(\lvert A \rvert =\lvert B \rvert\) then \(\exists\) a bijective \(h: A\rightarrow B\)
Composition
Suppose \(f:A\rightarrow B, g:B\rightarrow C\), then the composition is \(g\circ f:A\rightarrow C\)
Theorem 12.1: If \(f:A\rightarrow B\), \(g:B\rightarrow C\), \(h:C\rightarrow D\), then \((h\circ g)\circ f=h\circ (g\circ f)\)
Theorem 12.2: If \(f:A\rightarrow B\) and \(g: B\rightarrow C\), if both \(f\) and \(g\) are injective, then \(g\circ f\) is injective
Inverse Function
For a bijective \(f:A\rightarrow B\), its inverse is the function \(f^{-1}:B\rightarrow A\).
Composition with inverse yields identity function:
- \[f^{-1}\circ f = i_A\]
- \[f\circ f^{-1}=i_B\]
Identity Function
\[\forall x\in A, i_A(x)=x\]Theorem 12.3: Function \(f\) is bijective iff the reverse relation \(f^{-1}\) is a function \(B\rightarrow A\)
Image & Preimage
Suppose \(f:A\rightarrow B\):
- If \(X\subset A\), the image of \(X\) is the set \(f(X)=\{f(x):x\in X\}\subset B\)
- If \(Y\subset B\), the preimage of \(Y\) is the set \(f^{-1}(Y)=\{f^{-1}(y):y\in Y\}\subset A\)
Chapter 13
…
Useful Definitions and Facts
Parity & Multiplicity
- An integer \(n\) is even iff if \(n=2a\) for some \(a\in\mathbb Z\)
- An integer \(n\) is odd iff \(n=2a+1\) for some \(a\in\mathbb Z\)
- Integers \(k\) and \(n\) have the same parity if \(k\) and \(n\) are both even or odd.
- An integer \(n\) is a multiple of an integer \(q\) iff \(n=qk\) for some \(k\in \mathbb Z\)
- A positive integer \(n\) is a prime number iff \(n\) has exactly two positive divisors, namely \(1\) and \(n\).
Well-Ordering Principle
- Given a subset \(A\subset \mathbb N\), and \(A\neq \emptyset\), then there is an element \(x_0\in A\) such that \(x_0\) is the smallest element in \(A\)
- Given an integer \(b\), any non-empty subset \(A\subset\{b, b+1, b+2,\dots\}\) is well-ordered
Division Algorithm
- Given integers \(a\) and \(b > 0\), there exists integer \(q\) and \(r\) for which \(a=gb+r\) and \(0\leq r \lt b\)
Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic
- Every integer greater than 1 is either a prime number itself or is the product of prime numbers
Greatest Common Divisor & Least Common Multiple
Given \(k,n\in (\mathbb Z-\{0\})\),
- The GCD of \(k\) and \(n\) is the largest integer that divides both \(k\) and \(n\)
- The LCM of \(k\) and \(n\) is the smallest integer that is a multiple of both \(k\) and \(n\)
Proposition 7.1
If \(a,b\in \mathbb N\), then there exists integers \(k\) and \(l\) for which \(\gcd(a,b)=ak+bl\)
Proposition 10.1
Suppose there are \(n\geq2\) integers \(a_1, a_2, \dots, a_n\). If a prime number \(p\) divides \(a_1\cdot a_2\cdots a_n\), then \(p\) divides at least one of the integers \(a_i\).
Congruence
- Given \(n\in \mathbb N, a,b\in \mathbb Z\), \(a\) is congruent to \(b\mod n\), denoted by \(a\equiv b\mod n\), iff \(n\mid a-b\)
Assuming \(a\equiv b\mod n\) and \(c\equiv d\mod n\) for \(a,b,c,d\in \mathbb Z\), then:
- \[a-c\equiv b-d\mod n\]
- \[a^2\equiv b^2\mod n\]
- \[ac\equiv bd \mod n\]
- If \(a\equiv b \mod n\) and \(b \equiv c \mod n\) then
Pigeonhole Principle
see above
Image & Preimage
Theorem 12.4: Suppose \(f: A\rightarrow B\) and \(W,X\subset A, Y,Z\subset B\)
- \[f(W\cap X)\subset f(W)\cap f(X)\]
- \[f(W\cup X)=f(W)\cup f(X)\]
- \[f^{-1}(Y\cap Z)=f^{-1}(Y)\cap f^{-1}(Z)\]
- \[f^{-1}(Y\cup Z)=f^{-1}(Y)\cup f^{-1}(Z)\]
- \[X\subset f^{-1}(f(X))\]
- \[f(f^{-1}(Y))\subset Y\]